Wednesday, 8 May 2019

Alvin Plantinga on Divine Impassibility, Passibility, and the Incarnation: A Few Considerations

I have recently enjoyed reading Prof Alvin Plantinga's Knowledge and Christian Belief (KCB). It is a very well written book. Being an abridged and revised version of the much bigger Warranted Christian Belief, KCB not only offers a good introduction to Prof Plantinga's philosophy but it also contains a good overview of the academic issues it discusses. There are a few minor disagreements I have with Prof Plantinga's epistemological and apologetic treatment on the rationality and warrant of theistic Christian belief, and here I will not mention any of these issues. However, I came across a section of this book that I found both unexpected (in the light of the specific nature of the volume) and weak. In this section, Prof Plantinga denies the classical Christian doctrine of divine impassibility, claiming that the incarnation of Christ makes it severely problematic. The doctrine of divine impassibility is as follows.
“Impassibility is that divine attribute whereby God is said not to experience inner emotional changes of state whether enacted freely from within or effected by his relationship to and interaction with human beings and the created order. More specifically, impassibility means that God does not experience suffering and pain, and thus does not have feelings that are analogous to human feelings. Divine impassibility follows upon His immutability, in that, since God is changeless and unchangeable, his inner emotional state cannot change from joy to sorrow or from delight to suffering.” ~ Thomas Weinandy, "Impassibility of God," in New Catholic Encyclopedia: Vol. 7, 357. (Note: the definition rightly connects impassibility and immutability, and I will referr to both these doctrines).
Differently, Prof Plantinga says what follows.
"I believe God can and does suffer; his capacity for suffering exceeds ours in the same measure that his knowledge exceeds ours. Christ’s suffering was no charade; he was prepared to endure the agonies of the cross and of hell itself ('My God, my God, why have you forsaken me?'). God the Father was prepared to endure the anguish of seeing his Son, the second person of the trinity, consigned to the bitterly cruel and shameful death of the cross. And isn’t the same true for other passions? 'There is more rejoicing in heaven over one sinner who repents than over ninety-nine righteous persons who do not need to repent' (Luke 15:7); is God himself to be excluded from this rejoicing?" ~ KCB, 77.
Prof Plantinga's denial seems rather out of place and unexpected because his argument works equally well also assuming the traditional view of God's impassibility. But I am getting ahead of myself. 

The Context of the Argument
It is not necessary to give a detailed overview of KCB's goal. For clarity's sake, it is sufficient to say that his book is dedicated to demonstrating how the religious beliefs of a Christian believer "enjoy justification, rationality, and warrant" (KCB, 70), independently of whether the believer is philosophically, theologically or scientifically trained or not. Plantinga defines warrant as follows.
"A belief has warrant for a person S only if that belief is produced by cognitive faculties [such as perception, memory, introspection, reason, and testimony] functioning properly (subject to no dysfunction) in a cognitive environment that is appropriate for S's kind of cognitive faculties, according to a design plan that is successfully aimed at truth." ~ KCB, 28.
Again, I will not go through Prof Plantinga's book because it is not necessary for my current purpose. There are several reviews and summaries available online for those who are interested. Alternatively, the reader might read the book itself, which is easy to read and not long. It is sufficient to say at this point that in chapters 1 and 2, Prof Plantinga offers a summary of the academic debate. In chapters 3 to 5, Prof Plantinga discusses and argues for the warrant of holding, not only belief in God, but belief in the triune God of Christianity and Jesus Christ the incarnate Word of God.  

Divine impassibility?
Chapter 6 continues what Prof Plantinga already started in chapter 5, that is, discussing the affective and volitional side of Christian faith and belief in addition to the intellectual one. Close to the end of the chapter, however, severe problems start to arise. Prof Plantinga wants to argue that, within the life of the three persons of the Trinity, there is love. This is a rather uncontroversial claim which is held (albeit with different explanations) throughout the entire Christian theological tradition, starting from "God is love" (1 John 4:8) to the present day. Prof Plantinga argues for a specific kind of love: eros. Erotic love, as Prof Plantinga defines it, is "longing, desire, a desire for some kind of union ... " (KCB, 74). The Bible ascribes this love to the three persons of the Trinity and, Prof Plantinga claims, is, therefore, incompatible with the classical Christian doctrine of divine impassibility. Prof Plantinga defines and describes the latter doctrine as follows.
"Now a widely shared traditional view of God has been that he is impassible, without desire or feeling or passion, unable to feel sorrow at the sad condition of his world and the suffering of his children, and equally unable to feel joy, delight, longing, or yearning. The reason for so thinking, roughly, is that in the tradition originating in Greek philosophy, passions were thought of (what else?) as passive, something that happens to you, something you undergo, rather than something you actively do. You are subject to and undergo anger, love, joy, and all the rest. God, however, doesn't undergo anything at all; he acts, and is never merely passive; and he isn't subject to anything. As far as eros is concerned, furthermore, there is an additional reason for thinking that it isn't part of God's life: longing and yearning signify need and incompleteness. One who yearns for something doesn't yet have it, and needs it, or at any rate thinks he needs it; God is of course paradigmatically complete and needs nothing beyond himself. How, then, could he be subject to eros? God's love, according to this tradition, is exclusively agape, benevolence, a completely other-regarding, magnanimous love in which there is mercy but no element of desire. God loves us, but there is nothing we can do for him; he wishes nothing from us." (KCB, 76-77). 
I believe that the quotation above does not accurately describe the classical Christian theistic view of God's impassibility, and I will attempt to show why. As a disclaimer, I am not arguing that Prof Plantinga has nowhere offered better support for his claims, and I will limit my analysis to the sixth chapter of KCB.

Actus Purus and the Incarnation
In Prof Plantinga's account there is an element that Prof Plantinga briefly mentions but that is not sufficiently discussed in his description of divine impassibility, that is, that God is actus purus (pure act, or purely active). This is an essential point because if we want to accept or reject an idea, it is important to have a proper view of that idea in front of our eyes. 

The God of classical Christian theism is a purely active God, "most high, most excellent, most potent, most omnipotent; most piteous and most just; most hidden and most near; most beauteous and most strong, stable, yet contained of none; unchangeable, yet changing all things; never new, never old; making all things new, yet bringing old age upon the proud and they know it not; always working, yet ever at rest; gathering, yet needing nothing; sustaining, pervading, and protecting; creating, nourishing, and developing; seeking, and yet possessing all things. You love, and burn not; You are jealous, yet free from care; You repent, and have no sorrow; You are angry, yet serene; You change Your ways, leaving unchanged Your plans; You recover what You find, having yet never lost; You are never in want, while You rejoice in gain; You are never covetous, though requiring usury" (Augustine, Confessions, 1.4.4).

In order to have a proper view of classical Christian theism, when we mention God's impassibility it is essential to properly mention also the other side of this doctrine, that is, God's utter actuality. Stephen Charnock describes God's pure actuality and absolute  and blessed fullness of being in reference to the believers' future state of glory.
"The enjoyment of God will be as fresh and glorious after many ages, as it was at first. God is eternal, and eternity knows no change; there will then be the fullest possession without any decay in the object enjoyed. There can be nothing past, nothing future; time neither adds to it, nor detracts from it; that infinite fulness of perfection which flourisheth in him now, will flourish eternally, without any discoloring of it in the least, by those innumerable ages that shall run to eternity, much less any despoiling him of them: 'He is the same in his endless duration' (Psalm 102:27). As God is, so will the eternity of him be, without succession, without division; the fulness of joy will be always present; without past to be thought of with regret for being gone; without future to be expected with tormenting desires. When we enjoy God, we enjoy him in his eternity without any flux; an entire possession of all together, without the passing away of pleasures that may be wished to return, or expectation of future joys which might be desired to hasten. Time is fluid, but eternity is stable; and after many ages, the joys will be as savory and satisfying as if they had been but that moment first tasted by our hungry appetites. When the glory of the Lord shall rise upon you, it shall be so far from ever setting, that after millions of years are expired, as numerous as the sands on the seashore, the sun, in the light of whose countenance you shall live, shall be as bright as at the first appearance; he will be so far from ceasing to flow, that he will flow as strong, as full, as at the first communication of himself in glory to the creature. God, therefore, as sitting upon his throne of grace, and acting according to his covenant, is like a jasper-stone, which is of a green color, a color always delightful (Rev. 4:3); because God is always vigorous and flourishing; a pure act of life, sparkling new and fresh rays of life and light to the creature, flourishing with a perpetual spring, and contenting the most capacious desire; forming your interest, pleasure, and satisfaction; with an infinite variety, without any change or succession; he will have variety to increase delights, and eternity to perpetuate them; this will be the fruit of the enjoyment of an infinite and eternal God: be is not a cistern, but a fountain, wherein water is always living, and never putrefies." ~ Stephen Charnock, The Existence and Attributes of God, Volume 1, 298-299.
God's immutability and impassibility point to God's pure actuality, absolute perfection, blessed fullness, and absolute lack of any need. Quite rightly, R. D. Culver titled the chapter of his Systematic Theology dedicated to divine impassibility: "God's Blessedness, or Impassibility" (216; emphasis mine). Missing this point means giving an inaccurate account of the doctrine at issue. 

There is also another point that is absent from Prof Plantinga's account which only initially seems minor. Prof Plantinga says that in the classical Christian view of God, "God is impassible, without desire or feeling or passion, unable to feel sorrow at the sad condition of his world and the suffering of his children, and equally unable to feel joy, delight, longing, or yearning" (KCB, 76). Although these statements are correct, they offer a partial and mutilated view of classical Christian (i.e., incarnational) theism. Prof Plantinga has left out the unmeasurable amount of ink that classical Christian theists have used to expound and discuss God's sympathy in the incarnation of the Word"Seeing then that we have a great high priest, that is passed into the heavens, Jesus the Son of God, let us hold fast our profession. For we have not an high priest which cannot be touched with the feeling of our infirmities; but was in all points tempted like as we are, yet without sin. Let us therefore come boldly unto the throne of grace, that we may obtain mercy, and find grace to help in time of need" (Hebrews 4:14-16, KJV). John Calvin says as follows.
"Another principal part of our reconciliation with God was, that man, who had lost himself by his disobedience, should, by way of remedy, oppose to it obedience, satisfy the justice of God, and pay the penalty of sin. Therefore, our Lord came forth very man, adopted the person of Adam, and assumed his name, that he might in his stead obey the Father; that he might present our flesh as the price of satisfaction to the just judgment of God, and in the same flesh pay the penalty which we had incurred. Finally, since as God only he could not suffer, and as man only could not overcome death, he united the human nature with the divine, that he might subject the weakness of the one to death as an expiation of sin, and by the power of the other, maintaining a struggle with death, might gain us the victory." ~ John Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion2.12.3.
Just like God's pure actuality, God's condescension and mercy in Christ cannot be missing from an accurate account of classical Christian theism. In fact, I could give many other references from eminent Christian thinkers who skilfully describe both God's immutable and impassible being and His condescension in the incarnation, where the former is a reason that magnifies God's condescension in the incarnation. See, among many examples, Anselm of Canterbury's Cur Deus Homo; TurretinInstitutes of Elenctic Theology: Vol 2, 302-303; Peter Sanlon, Simply God, 122-143.

KCB's lack of proper references to similar key elements of the traditional view of God (God as purely active and the incarnation) is a flaw that should not be overlooked. With these missing links in mind, we now have a more accurate and heart-warming picture of classical Christian theism. 

AgapeEros, and Impassibility
Let us, for the sake of argument, assume a distinction between erotic love and agape love, a distinction that is key to Prof Plantinga's claims. According to Prof Plantinga, the God of classical theism cannot posses eros love, but only agape love. This is because, according to him, eros implies "longing and yearning" which "signify need and incompleteness" (KCB, 76). "One who yearns for something," Prof Plantinga continues, "doesn't yet have it, and needs it, or at any rate thinks he needs it; God is of course paradigmatically complete and needs nothing beyond himself. How, then, could he be subject to eros? God's love, according to this tradition, is exclusively agape" (KCB, 76). Contrary to the "traditional view of God," erotic love, Prof Plantinga claims, can and has to be ascribed to the life of the Trinity.  
"According to Jonathan Edwards, 'The infinite happiness of the Father consists in the enjoyment of His Son.' This presumably isn’t agape. It doesn’t involve an element of mercy, as in his love for us. It is, instead, a matter of God’s taking enormous pleasure, enjoyment, delight, happiness, delectation in the Son. Given the necessary existence of the Father and the Son, and their having their most important properties essentially, there is no way in which God could be deprived of the Son; but if (per impossible) he were, it would occasion inconceivable sadness. The love in question is eros, not agape. It is a desire for union that is continually, eternally, and joyfully satisfied." ~ KCB, 77-78.
Prof Plantinga's claims, nevertheless, are far from being obvious. 

First of all, the essential meaning of "longing" and "yearning" is to strongly will something. The absence of the thing yearned or longed for is an accidental and unnecessary element that Prof Plantinga adds to the essential meaning of the terms. In fact, the Cambridge Dictionary defines "yearn" as "to desire something strongly, especially [but not exclusively] something difficult or impossible to obtain," and "long" as "to want something very much [absence of that something is not necessary to the definition]". The same is true for the definitions found in the Oxford Dictionary. In fact, a husband may deeply and strongly yearn and long for his wife even in the very moment when the two are physically very close to each other, and there is not the slightest contradiction in such a state of things.

Secondly, in the preceding pages of his book (KCB, 74-76), Prof Plantinga gives a very brief overview with definitions (referring mostly to William James and Jean-Paul Sartre) to explain why eros and agape love cannot be placed together in the God of classical Christin theism. Also here, however, the treatment is not easy to follow. The treatment seems quite ad hoc inasmuch as it defines eros and agape in a certain way (as we have seen above) only to conclude that it is not applicable to an impassible God. Moreover, apart from a few anecdotal examples that Prof Plantinga quotes, it seems to find a good number of counterexamples from the Christian tradition. In fact, theologian Thomas C. Oden (who held to divine immutability and impassibility) sees no conflict whatsoever in placing both agape and eros in the immutable and impassible life of God
"Although agapē and eros seem to be opposites, they may come together and flow in balanced simultaneity and support each other's impulses. Both are expressions of the inestimably high value the heart sets upon that which is loved. Both involve a prizing: Love prizes the beloved so earnestly that it cannot rest without its possession (eros), without experiencing the completion of itself in the other. Love prizes the beloved so highly that it does not withhold any feasible gift or service (agapē). Both involve a yearning: love as eros yearns for the self's fulfillment through another; love as agapē yearns for the other's fulfillment even at a cost to oneself. To separate eros and agapē or to oppose them or set them sharply off against each other may fail to understand how one dimension may strengthen the other." ~ Thomas C. Oden, Systematic Theology: Vol. 1: The Living God, 119 (Note: Oden's full section offers a more historically comprehensive account of eros and agape than the one offered by Prof Plantinga).
The Trinity
Prof Plantinga claims that "given the necessary existence of the Father and the Son, and their having their most important properties essentially, there is no way in which God could be deprived of the Son," adding in a footnote that "this is the answer to one of the traditional arguments for the conclusion that God has no passions: the Father and the Son do indeed need each other, but it is a need that is necessarily and eternally fulfilled" (KCB, 78).

Prof Plantinga does not offer any explanation of why what he says in the footnote constitutes the answer to one of the traditional arguments for divine impassibility, and it is unclear why that should be the case. Rather, the eternal and necessary nature of the inter-trinitarian relationships that he mentions seems to play against his passibilistic claims. If the supposed "need" is necessarily and eternally fulfilled, then the fact is that there is not, there has never been, and there will never be any real need whatsoever in the inter-trinitarian relationships because, in this case, “there is no state of the Father that is not a begetting of the Son, and no state of the Son which is not a being begotten by the Father … There is no possible world where the Father exists and not the Son” (P. Helm, Eternal God, 285-286). There has never been a "need" to begin with, and this because Father-Son-Holy Spirit are just what they are and it is absolutely impossible that they cannot not be what they are. Therefore, the concept of "need" can be used in reference to the triune life of God only for explanatory purposes, and not concretely, as Prof Plantinga's position seems to require.

It is, therefore, fully possible to maintain that the three Persons of the immutable and impassible triune God exercise both agape and eros towards each other. Saying that the Father longs and yearns to dwell with the Son and that the Son longs and yearns to dwell in the Father through the Spirit does not necessarily imply any passibility, mutability, or lack (as Prof Plantinga claims). The Father does not become the Father, nor the Son become the Son, nor the Holy Spirit become the Holy Spirit. The three persons are in eternal relationship to each other so that the Father is eternally the Father, the Son is eternally the Son, and the Holy Spirit is eternally the Holy Spirit. The Father eternally begets the Son. We read of the eternal generation of the Son in John 1:14, John 3:16 and Psalm 2 (even though this Psalm talks primarily of Christ’s resurrection, as Acts 13:33 tells us). The Son is different from the Father inasmuch as the Father is the logical source of the Deity and he is the Person who plans and leads the plan of salvation. The Son is eternally generated by the Father and is the Person who reveals in time through his incarnation the plan of redemption of the Father. The Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son and applies the redemption in time. The eternal generation, begetting of the Son is:
"An act of both the Father and the Son, of the one generating and one generated, actively performed by the Father, passively accomplished by the Son. Scripture explicitly refers to the generation of the Son (Psalm 2:7) and to the fact that the Son is beloved (dilectus: Matt. 4:17; 17;5), the proper (propius) Son of God (John 5:18; Rom. 8:32), and only begotten (unigenitus: John 1:14, 18; 3:16; 1 John 4:9). This generation is, moreover, eternal and perpetual, and unlike the generations of things in the physical world. Marckius argues, thus, that the generation of the Son is not a physical but a 'hyperphysical generation from which–as in the via negativa approach to the attributes–all 'imperfection, dependence, succession, mutation, division, and multiplication' is absent. Nonetheless, this is a 'proper,' not a 'metaphysical,' generation, a genuine filiation flowing (fluens) from the Father according to which the Son is the true image of the invisible God, the representation of the glory and character of the Father’s person (cf. Col. 1:15; Heb. 1:3). By this generation, the Son is 'produced from the Father' in an 'eternal and incomprehensible communication of the unitary divine essence.'" ~ Richard A. Muller, Post-Reformation Reformed Dogmatics: Volume 4: The Triunity of God, 287.
Simply assuming definitions of love that necessarily require passibility and mutability to work, and then applying them to the inter-trinitarian relationship of the divine Being, seems somewhat question-begging.
“Clearly, in a finite essence, generation implies some sort of division or separation–but in the infinite, simple divine essence, generation does not indicate a division or separation, much less a partitioning of the divine essence … The claim that such a generation is impossible, [John] Owen comments, rests on the error of arguing limitations of the divine on the basis of ‘properties and attendancies of that which is finite.’” ~ Muller, Post-Reformation Reformed Dogmatics: Volume 4: The Triunity of God, 287.
It is fully correct to say that God eternally begets the Son in infinite love, either eros or agape love. But this love is not something outside himself or even something that has a start inside himself, but it is the Holy Spirit himself (Augustine, On the Trinity, 6.5.7; Anselm, Monologion, 49-55; Thomas Aquinas, Compendium of Theology, 45-46; Jonathan Edwards, “Discourse on the Trinity,” 121-132), coequal and coeternal with the Father and the Son, so that God's simplicity, sufficiency and impassibility are preserved, since God has all that he "needs" (so to speak!) eternally and necessarily in Himself for the inter-trinitarian life. 

God's relationship with creatures does not change what has been said. His people are in Christ before the foundation of the world (Ephesians 1), and they are included into Christ by the operation of the Holy Spirit present in them (2 Corinthians 16:14) so that they are in God and God is in them. In this, the believers change and something is added to them, but nothing changes and nothing is added to God. We can consider the many Scriptural references that describe God's saving desire towards elect humans as efficaciously satisfied not only in time ("All that the Father giveth me [to Christ] shall come to me" John 6:37; John 10) but also in and "from" eternity (Ephesians 1-2; Romani 8). See Augustine for some more on this.

The Incarnation, Again
"Can we say that Christ qua human being (according to his human nature) suffered while Christ qua divine (according to his divine nature) did not? This is hardly the place to try to address a question as ancient and deep as this one, but I'm inclined to think this suggestion incoherent. There is this person, the second person of the divine trinity who became incarnate. It is this person who suffers; if there really were two centers of consciousness here, one suffering and the other not, there would be two persons here (one human and one divine) rather than the one person who is both human and divine." ~ KCB, 77.
Prof Plantinga says that "this is hardly the place to try to address a question as ancient and deep as this one" (KCB, 77). However, answering this question is foundational for the entire structure of his discourse. In this regard, Prof Plantinga's claim collapses because of the way he frames the issue. His argument can be summarised as follows.
a.) According to classical Christian theism, Christ suffered only according to his human nature, and not as according to his divine nature. 
b.) a  implies "two centres of consciousness," one suffering (the human nature) and the other not (the divine nature). 
c.)  implies "two persons here (one human and one divine) rather than the one person who is both human and divine." 
d.) is unorthodox (a sort of Nestorianism). 
e.) Therefore, a is false.
This is a rather confused argument. a is the classical Christian position. However, Prof Plantinga interprets it not according to its own classical Christian theological categories, but according to the terms found in b which are not the theological categories through which a is usually explained. Prof Plantinga's theological categories of b ("three centres of consciousness") belong to the recent reformulation of the doctrine of the Trinity. To interpret the classical position through contemporary categories only to conclude that the classical position is wrong is simply circular reasoning.

a does not imply b ("two centres of consciousness," whatever Prof Plantinga means with that, he does not define it in the chapter). Therefore, c is false. a implies two natures, one suffering and the other not. "Nature" does not necessarily equal "centre of consciousness" and, therefore, it is correct to say that there are not two persons (as premise c mistakenly says) but one person and two natures. For these reasons, Prof Plantinga's argument does not pose any problem for a (and, by implication, for the doctrine of divine impassibility) simply because it uses terms and categories (b and c) that do not belong to a and that a actually rejects at the very outset.
"Others ... have had recourse to the supposition of a twofold personality in the Saviour—holding that the Son of God, when He became incarnate, united Himself to 'the man Christ Jesus,' and that the union between these two persons was somewhat the same in kind with that which is constituted by the indwelling of the Holy Spirit in believers, although doubtless much more intimate and indissoluble. This notion also is at variance with the facts of the case. For, so far as we are taught in Scripture, the human nature of our Lord never had any existence by itself as a distinct and separate person. It existed from the first, and still continues to exist, in union with the divine nature of the Son of God, and no otherwise. The incarnation, therefore, is not at all the case of one person joining himself to another person; but the case of one person, possessed of the divine nature, assuming the nature and attributes of humanity into union with those of divinity which had previously pertained to Him. 
How this was done, it would very ill become us, in the silence of revelation, to conjecture. But, that it was done, is the plain doctrine of the Scriptures. They everywhere speak of the Saviour as one person, although they ascribe to Him, in His incarnate state, such a union of human with divine attributes as is nowhere else to be found in one person. In some passages they represent Him as divine, while in other passages they represent Him as human; but both of these representations are applicable to one and the same person, Jesus Christ our Lord. Nay, sometimes, when He is denominated by one or other of His divine titles, we find things said of Him which are only attributable to His human nature, as when we read that 'the Lord of glory was crucified' (1 Cor. 2:8) and sometimes also, when He is denominated by one or other of His human titles, we find things said of Him which are only attributable to His divine nature, as when 'the Son of Man' is said to have 'come down from heaven.' This 'communion of attributes,' as it has been called—when things which properly pertain to the one nature are ascribed to Christ when designated with reference to the other nature—evidently implies the sameness of the person to whom both classes of names and attributes equally belong, and who, as possessing both, may have the one in combination with the other appropriately assigned to Him." ~ T. J. Crawford (1812-1875), The Mysteries of Christianity, 205-206 (for more on the issue of the communication of attributes [communicatio idiomatum], see Francis Turretin, Institutes of Elenctic Theology: Vol 2, 321-332; Herman Bavinck, Reformed Dogmatics: Vol. 3, 308-316).
For more on this, see Turretin, Institutes of Elenctic Theology: Vol 2, 310-321; Bavinck, Our Reasonable Faith, 326-327; Reformed Dogmatics: Vol. 3, 256-259, 298-308. I warmly suggest reading W. G. T. Shedd, Dogmatic Theology, 613-644 (especially the section "Incarnation and Divine Immutability"), 649-658. In addition to being clearly written, Shedd's pages are a good corrective for most (if not all) the misunderstandings contained in Prof Plantinga's argument. Shedd's Dogmatic Theology can also be found online.

Final Issues
"The thought that God is triune distinguishes Christianity from other theistic religions; here we see a way in which this doctrine makes a real difference, in that it recognizes eros and love for others at the most fundamental level of reality. Does this suggest that we should lean toward a social conception of the trinity, the conception of Gregory and the Cappadocian fathers, rather than the Augustinian conception, which flirts with modalism?" ~ KCB, 78. Emphasis added.
The reader should not take these claims at face value. They are swift and inaccurate generalizations which require long answers. However, suffice here to say the same kind of claims Prof Plantinga's makes (the ones in italic) broadly belong to the recent reformulations of trinitarian thinking and have been heavily disputed by many scholars. For instance, "social trinitarianism is a recent departure from classic Trinitarianism and provides an alternative answer to how God is one in essence and three in person: the three persons are distinguished not by their relations of origin but by relationships. That is, the three persons of God each possess what we would call a personality, including a distinct volitional will, and how these relate to one another is what distinguishes Father, Son, and Spirit. Typically, both the economic roles and the volitional relationships that bind them (e.g., eternal material subordination) distinguish Father, Son, and Spirit" (M. Y. Emerson, "The Role of Proverbs 8: Eternal Generation and Hermeneutics Ancient and Modern," in Retrieving Eternal Generation, 46). Here, I will limit myself to give suggestions for further reading.

The claim that the Cappadocian Fathers supported what is today called "social trinitarianism" is, at the very best, highly doubtful.  Rather, many have argued that "social trinitarianism [is] a seemingly modern innovation and one lacking in biblical warrant" (Emerson, "The Role of Proverbs 8," 65). See, among several examples, Stephen R. Holmes, The Quest for the Trinity, 30-32, 56-146.

Prof Plantinga also claims that the classical doctrine of divine impassibility "is one of those places where it has paid too much attention to Greek philosophy and too little to the Bible" (page 77). In this case also, this grandiose claim (as it intends to cover over 2000 years of Christian theological production in just a few words) is without any support and is, in fact, misleading. See, among many examples, see Vv.Aa., Confessing the Impassible God, 89-223; R. B. Culver, Systematic Theology: Biblical and Historical, 216-225.

Augustine is certainly not the last word, but the claim that his doctrine of the Trinity "flirts with modalism" (KCB, 78) is very far from being an uncontroversial statement and, in my opinion, mistaken. See, among several examples, Lewis Ayres, Augustine and the Trinity.

Passibility Unproved (and Unnecessary)
Simply put, divine passibility is left without any successful philosophical argument in the section of Prof Plantinga's KCB I have examined. This is true also theologically inasmuch as simply quoting a few biblical passages is neither arguing nor exegeting. Prof Plantinga quotes Matthew 27:46 and Luke 15:7, and Isaiah 62:5, but he does not explain why they are supposed to support his theological claims. For developed discussions on this issue (the so-called "communication of attributes or properties," communicatio idiomatum), see the references at the end of the indented quote from T. J. Crawford. 

More importantly and even more puzzling is the fact that Prof Plantinga's epistemological argument for the warranted nature of Christian belief does not need divine passibility in order to work. The goal of chapter 6 was to expand the volitional and affective side of his epistemological model. That model requires mutable and passible receptiveness from the finite moral agents who become involved in and recipients of the salvific work of God, and the chapter does not explain at all why said epistemological model should require mutability and passibility in God himself. Nevertheless, Prof Plantinga unexpectedly brings up a controversial doctrine (divine passibility) that is philosophically unnecessary for his epistemological argument and that does not have any sufficient exegetical or theological support in the section I have examined. Why such tangential and unsubstantiated theological claims are extensively mentioned in the middle of the good argument of a good book is, for me, hard to understand.

©

Monday, 29 April 2019

Herman Bavinck on Faith and Works

Herman Bavinck (1854-1921).
Disclaimer: in spite of its length, what follows is only a small part of a much longer discussion that Herman Bavinck (1854–1921) offers on the topic of justification. For Bavinck's fuller treatment, see Chapter 3 of the work referenced at the end of the quotation.
"It [is] possible for us to regard faith as simultaneously a receptive organ and an active power. If in every respect justification comes after faith, faith becomes a condition, an activity that has to be performed in advance and cannot be purely receptive. But if the righteousness on the basis of which we are justified exists completely outside of us in Christ Jesus, it can naturally be appropriated by us only because we accept it in childlike faith. 'The forgiveness of sins is a thing promised for Christ's sake. Therefore it can be accepted only by faith, since a promise can be accepted only on faith' (Apology of the Augsburg Confession, art. 4, pars. 40-47). Faith, therefore, is not the material or formal cause of justification; it is not even a condition or instrument (instrumental cause) of justification, for it does not relate to justification as, for example, the eye to seeing or the ear to hearing. Faith is not a condition on which, and not an instrument or organ by which, we receive this benefit, but the very act of accepting Christ and all his benefits as he by his Word and Spirit offers himself to us, and faith therefore includes the consciousness that he is my Lord and that I am his possession. Faith therefore is not an instrument in the true sense, one that serves as the means by which a person accepts Christ, bur is a sure knowledge and firm confidence that the Holy Spirit works in one's heart and by which he [the Spirit] persuades and assures people that, despite all their sins, they share in Christ and all his benefits.

But if this is saving faith, it cannot be a 'knowledge of history' or a 'bare assent' to certain truths; then it is by in very nature a living and active faith, and it is nor in every respect antithetical to all work. It constitutes a contrast to the works of the law in a double sense, that is, in the fact that the latter can neither be the material nor the instrumental cause of justification. It is also antithetical to the works of faith (infused righteousness, obedience, love) the moment these are in even the slightest degree regarded as a ground for justification, as constituting in part or in whole the righteousness on the basis of which God justifies us. For that is Christ and Christ alone. Faith itself is not a ground for justification; neither, therefore, are the works that proceed from it. 

But faith is not opposed to working if by it one should mean that only a dead inactive faith can justify us. For the dispute between Rome and the Reformation was not about whether we are justified by an active or an inactive faith, by a living or a dead faith. But the question was, as it was for Paul, whether faith with its works justifies us before God or in our conscience, or whether faith justifies apart from works. Nor is faith opposed to the works of faith insofar as these works, as the fruits of faith, are used by the Holy Spirit to assure believers of the genuineness of their faith and thus of their salvation. In this sense faith itself is even a work (John 6:29), the best work and the principle of all good works. The Reformed therefore also said that indeed, 'it is faith alone that justifies: nevertheless the faith that justifies is not alone,' and spoke, in addition to 'the justification of the sinner' also of a 'justification of the righteous.' In this sense Paul and James are also in agreement. Granted, it is not correct to say that Paul speaks only of the 'justification of the sinner' whereas James speaks of the 'justification of the righteous.' Bur both deny that the ground of our justification consists in the works of the law, and both acknowledge that faith, that is, living faith, the faith that includes and produces good works, is the means by which the Holy Spirit assures us of our righteousness in Christ. In this connection the only difference is that Paul fights against dead works while James wages a campaign against a dead faith. The faith that justifies is the certainty—produced in our hearts by the Holy Spirit—of our righteousness in Christ. Therefore, not the more passive but the more lively and forceful it is, the more it justifies us. Faith, accordingly, is active along with works and is 'brought to completion by the works' (James 2:22)."
Herman Bavinck, Reformed Dogmatics: Vol. 4: Holy Spirit, Church, and New Creation (Grand Rapids, Michigan: Baker Academic, 2008), 221-223.


Saturday, 13 April 2019

Zacharias Ursinus on "Why Good Works are to be Done, or Why are they Necessary?"

The following section from Commentary on the Heidelberg Catechism (pages 482-485) by Zacharias Ursinus (1534-1583), the main contributor to the writing of the Heidelberg Catechism (1563), is so helpful, theologically sound, and terminologically clear that I personally do not feel any need to add any further comment to Ursinus' excellent treatment. Ursinus' theological patience slowly guides the reader to his conclusions, and, at the same time, teaches him not to jump to conclusions or to deliver hasty judgements. In my view, his terminological clarity, together with the other qualities I mentioned, constitute an excellent example to follow while studying or discussing such important theological issues. I am almost tempted to make a poster out of it and stick it on the wall in front of my desk.

Ursinus seeks to answer an important question by dividing it into two parts: "Why good works are to be done, or why are they necessary?" Ursinus begins by answering the first part of the question, "Why good works are to be done", as follows. 
We have already, under the 86th Question, enumerated certain moving causes of good works which properly belong here; such as the connection which holds necessarily between regeneration and justification, the glory of God, the proof of our faith and election, and a good example by which others are won to Christ. These causes may be very appropriately dwelt upon to a much greater extent, if, having reduced them to three principal heads, we say that good works are to be performed by us for the sake of God, ourselves and our neighbor 
I. Good works are to be done in respect to God, 1. That the glory of God our heavenly Father, may be manifested. The manifestation of the glory of God is the chief end why God commands and wills that good works should be performed by us, that we may honor him by our good works, and that others seeing them may glorify our Father which is in heaven, as it is said, "Let your light so shine before men that they may see your good works, and glorify your Father which is in heaven" (Matt. 5:16). 2. That we may render unto God the obedience which he requires, or on account of the command of God. God requires the commencement of obedience in this life, and the perfection of it in the life to come. "This is my commandment, That ye love one another." "This is the will of God even your sanctification." "Being then made free from sin, ye became the servants of righteousness." "Yield your members as instruments of righteousness unto God." (John 15: 12; 1 Thes. 4: 3; Rom. 6:18, 13). 3. That we may thus render unto God the gratitude which we owe unto him. It is just and proper that we should love, worship and reverence him by whom we have been redeemed, and from whom we have received the greatest benefits, and that we should declare our love and gratitude by our obedience and good works. God deserves our obedience and worship on account of the benefits which he confers upon us. We do not merit his benefits by anything that we do. Hence our gratitude, which shows itself by our obedience and good works, is due unto God for his great benefits. "I beseech you, brethren, by the mercies of God, that ye present your bodies a living sacrifice, holy, acceptable unto God, which is your reasona ble service." "Ye are an holy priesthood to offer up spiritual sacrifices acceptable to God by Jesus Christ." (Rom. 12:1; 1 Pet. 2:5, 9, 20.)  
II. Good works are to be done on our own account, 1. That we may thereby testify our faith, and be assured of its existence in us by the fruits which we produce in our lives. "Every good tree bringeth forth good fruit." "Being filled with the fruits of righteousness which are by Jesus Christ, unto the praise and glory of God." "Faith without works is dead." (Matt. 7:17. Phil. 1:11. James 2:17). It is by our good works, therefore, that we know that we possess true faith, because the effect is not without its own proper cause, which is always known by its effect; so that if we are destitute of good works and new obedience, we are hypocrites, and have an evil conscience instead of true faith; for true faith (which is never wanting in all the fruits which are peculiar to it,) as a fruitful tree produces good works, obedience and repentance; which fruits distinguish true faith from that faith which is merely historical and temporary, as well as from hypocrisy itself. 2. That we may be assured of the fact that we have obtained the forgiveness of sins through Christ, and that we are justified for his sake. Justification and regeneration are benefits which are connected and knit together in such a way as never to be separated from each other. Christ obtained both for us at the same time, viz: the forgiveness of sins and the Holy Spirit, who through faith excites in us the desire of good works and new obedience. 3. That we may be assured of our election and salvation. "Give diligence to make your calling and election sure" (2 Pet. 1:10). This cause naturally grows out of the preceding one ; for God out of his mercy chose from everlasting only those who are justified on account of the merit of his Son. "Whom he did predestinate, them he also called ; and whom he called, them he also justified." (Rom. 8:30). We are, therefore, assured of our election by our justification; and that we are justified in Christ, (which benefit is never granted unto the elect without sanctification), we know from faith; of which we are, again, assured by the fruits of faith, which are good works, new obedience and true repentance. 4. That our faith may be exercised, nourished, strengthened and in creased by good works. Those who indulge in unclean lusts and desires against their consciences cannot have faith, and so are destitute of a good conscience and of confidence in God as reconciled and gracious; for it is only by faith that we obtain a sense of the divine favor towards us and a good conscience. "If ye live after the flesh, ye shall die." "I put thee in remembrance, that thou stir up the gift of God, which is in thee." (Rom. 8:13; 2 Tim. 1:6).5. That we may adorn and commend our profession, life and calling by our good works. "I beseech you, that ye walk worthy of the vocation wherewith ye are called." (Eph. 4:1). 6. That we may escape temporal and eternal punishment. "Every tree that bringeth not forth good fruit is hewn down and cast into the fire." "If ye live after the flesh ye shall die." " Thou with rebukes dost correct man for iniquity." (Matt. 7:19; Rom. 8:13; Ps. 39:11). 7. That we may obtain from God those temporal and spiritual rewards, which, according to the divine promise, accompany good works both in this and in a future life. "Godliness is profitable unto all things, having promise of the life that now is, and of that which is to come." (1 Tim. 4:8). And if God did not desire that the hope of reward, and the fear of punishment should be moving causes of good works, he would not use them as arguments in the promises and threatenings which he addresses unto us in his word.  
III Good works are to be done for the sake of our neighbor, 1. That we may be profitable unto our neighbor, and edify him by our example and godly conversation. "All things are for your sakes, that the abundant grace might, through the thanksgiving of many, redound to the glory of God," &c. "Nevertheless to abide in the flesh is more needful for you." (2 Cor. 4:15. Phil. 1:24).2. That we may not be the occasion of offences and scandal to the cause of Christ. "Woe to that man by whom the offence cometh." "The name of God is blasphemed among the Gentiles through you." (Matt. 18 : 7. Rom. 2 : 24).3. That we may win the unbelieving to Christ. "And when thou art converted, strengthen thy brethren." (Luke 22 : 32).
Ursinus proceeds to answer the second part of the question, "Whether good works are necessary for salvation," which, I believe, he does superbly.
The question, whether good works are necessary to salvation, belongs properly to this place. There have been some who have maintained simply and positively, that good works are necessary to salvation, while others, again, have held that they are pernicious and injurious to salvation. Both forms of speech are ambiguous and inappropriate, especially the latter; because it seems not only to condemn confidence, but also the desire of performing good works. It is, therefore, to be rejected. The former expression must be explained in this way; that good works are necessary to salvation, not as a cause to an effect, or as if they merited a reward, but as a part of salvation itself, or as an antecedent to a consequent, or as a means without which we cannot obtain the end. In the same way we may also say, that good works are necessary to righteousness or justification, or in them that are to be justified, viz.: as a consequence of justification, with which regeneration is inseparably connected. But yet we would prefer not to use these forms of speech, 1. Because they are ambiguous. 2. Because they breed contentions, and give our enemies room for caviling. 3. Because these expressions are not used in the Scriptures with which our forms of speech should conform as nearly as possible. We may more safely and correctly say, That good works are necessary in them that are justified, and that are to be saved. To say that good works are necessary in them that are to be justified, is to speak ambiguously, because it may be so understood as if they were required before justification, and so become a cause of our justification. Augustine has correctly said: “Good works do not precede them that are to be justified, but follow them that are justified” [Ursinus might have in mind Augustine's On Grace and Free Will, 17: "Works proceed from faith, and not faith from works"]. We may, therefore, easily return an answer to the following objection: that is necessary to salvation without which no one can be saved. But no one who is destitute of good works can be saved, as it is said in the 87th Question. Therefore, good works are necessary to salvation. We reply to the major proposition, by making the following distinction: that without which no one can be saved is necessary to salvation, viz.: as a part of salvation, or as a certain antecedent necessary to salvation, in which sense we admit the conclusion; but not as a cause, or as a merit of salvation. We, therefore, grant the conclusion of the major proposition if understood in the sense in which we have just explained it. For good works are necessary to salvation, or, to speak more properly, in them that are to be saved (for it is better thus to speak for the sake of avoiding ambiguity) as a part of salvation itself; or, as an antecedent of salvation, but not as a cause or merit of salvation.
This section belongs to Ursinus's commentary to Heidelberg Catechism, Question 91, "But what are good works? (pages 476-488 of the edition I linked above), a treatment that is well worth reading entirely.

©

Sunday, 24 February 2019

A Short but Meaningful Passage from Augustine

From "Theist Thug Life" FB Page.
Introduction
With the arrival of a new year (I know, I'm late) I thought to share something from Augustine of Hippo that has often encouraged me to meditate about time and eternity. The main reason why I love the following Augustinian text is that I remember reading this section from his Confessions years ago when I was still a teenager and my heart was not exactly at peace and my future uncertain. Antithetically to my own existence, the eternal and immutable nature of the triune God as described by this powerful statement provided me with some helpful and good for thought and, sure, some comfort. 
"Apud te rerum omnium instabilium stant causae et rerum omnium mutabilium immutabiles manent origines et omnium irrationalium et temporalium sempiternae vivunt rationes." ~ Confessiones, I.VI.IX. 
"In Thy presence do stand the causes of all things that are unstable and even of all things that are changeable the unchangeable roots remain with Thee, and the eternal reasons of things which are temporal and irrational do live." ~ Confessions, 1.6.9 (translation by Erich Przywara).
This beautiful statement by Augustine of Hippo, although brief, is so rich that it took me some time to decide where to start expounding its meaning. I will start by showing something of Augustine's beautiful theological rhetoric.
In Thy presence do stand the causes of all things that are unstable 
and even of all things that are changeable the unchangeable roots remain with Thee,
and the eternal reasons of things which are temporal and irrational do live.
If we associate the words which I have highlighted according to their colours, we will see that Augustine has composed a beautiful poem of theological juxtaposition of opposites, contraries, or antonyms (I thank David C. Noe for the hint). Thus, we arguably have something similar to what follows.

In Thy presence do:
a) stand the causes of all things that are unstable;
b) of all things that are changeable the unchangeable roots remain with Thee;
c₁) the eternal reasons of things which are temporal and irrational live;
c₂) the eternal reasons of things which are temporal and irrational live.

Here I am more interested in the theological and philosophical import of Augustine's words. The three couples of words are basically saying the same things, although each from a slightly different perspective. I will try to expound them separately. But first, we need to place Augustine's beautiful sentence in its context.

Some context
We are at the beginning of Augustine's Confessions. He began with a prayerful meditation on the nature of prayer, man and God (1.1.1 to 1.5.6). Then, he continues by meditating coram Deo (in the presence of God) about his birth and childhood, asking whence he "came hither into this—shall I call it dying life or living death?" (1.6.7). Augustine then reveals to be troubled by the very fact of the passing of the time, temporality itself raises in himself philosophical issues and existential questions.
"And, behold, my infancy died long ago, and I live ... Tell me, Your suppliant, O God; tell, O merciful One, Your miserable servant—tell me whether my infancy succeeded another age of mine which had at that time perished. Was it that which I passed in my mother's womb? For of that something has been made known to me, and I have myself seen women with child. And what, O God, my joy, preceded that life? Was I, indeed, anywhere, or anybody? For no one can tell me these things, neither father nor mother, nor the experience of others, nor my own memory. Do you laugh at me for asking such things, and command me to praise and confess You for what I know?" ~ Confessions, 1.6.9. 
Augustine realises that in order to understand and interpret both his present and past life, he has not so much to focus on his own memory of his youthfulness but rather he has to focus on the eternal and immutable God, creator of all.
"I give thanks to You, Lord of heaven and earth, giving praise to You for that my first being and infancy, of which I have no memory; for You have granted to man that from others he should come to conclusions as to himself, and that he should believe many things concerning himself on the authority of feeble women. Even then I had life and being; and as my infancy closed I was already seeking for signs by which my feelings might be made known to others. Whence could such a creature come but from You, O Lord? Or shall any man be skilful enough to fashion himself? Or is there any other vein by which being and life runs into us save this, that "You, O Lord, hast made us," with whom being and life are one, because You Yourself art being and life in the highest? You are the highest, "You change not" (Mal. 3:6), neither in You does this present day come to an end, though it does end in You, since in You all such things are; for they would have no way of passing away unless You sustained them. And since "Your years shall have no end," Your years are an ever present day. And how many of ours and our fathers' days have passed through this Your day, and received from it their measure and fashion of being, and others yet to come shall so receive and pass away! "But You are the same;" and all the things of tomorrow and the days yet to come, and all of yesterday and the days that are past, You will do today, You have done today. What is it to me if any understand not? Let him still rejoice and say, "What is this?" Let him rejoice even so, and rather love to discover in failing to discover, than in discovering not to discover You" ~ Confessions1.6.10.
The only solution to this problem is, for Augustine, to look outside of himself to what, or better, to the One who does not change.  
"You, O Lord, who ever livest, and in whom nothing dies, since before the world was, and indeed before all that can be called before, You exist, and are the God and Lord of all Your creatures; and with You fixedly abide the causes of all unstable things, the unchanging sources of all things changeable, and the eternal reasons of all things unreasoning and temporal." Confessions, 1.6.9. 

"In Thy presence do stand the causes of all things that are unstable." - Metaphysics. 
God is the supreme cause of everything. Augustine rejects all kinds of naturalism, deism, and, anyway, any doctrine that leaves anything outside of the sovereign and causative power and will of God. He does not deny the existence of secondary and created causes, but he points at the error of considering these causes as sufficient and independent of the power and will of God.
"There is one kind of natural order in the conversion and changeableness of bodies, which, although itself also serves the bidding of God, yet by reason of its unbroken continuity has ceased to cause wonder; as is the case, for instance, with those things which are changed either in very short, or at any rate not long, intervals of time, in heaven, or earth, or sea; whether it be in rising, or in setting, or in change of appearance from time to time; while there are other things, which, although arising from that same order, yet are less familiar on account of longer intervals of time. And these things, although the many stupidly wonder at them, yet are understood by those who inquire into this present world, and in the progress of generations become so much the less wonderful, as they are the more often repeated and known by more people. Such are the eclipses of the sun and moon, and some kinds of stars, appearing seldom, and earthquakes, and unnatural births of living creatures, and other similar things; of which not one takes place without the will of God; yet, that it is so, is to most people not apparent. And so the vanity of philosophers has found license to assign these things also to other causes, true causes perhaps, but proximate ones, while they are not able to see at all the cause that is higher than all others, that is, the will of God; or again to false causes, and to such as are not even put forward out of any diligent investigation of corporeal things and motions, but from their own guess and error." ~ On the Trinity, 3.2.7.
God's causative operation is comprehensive and includes not only the natural world but also the moral and spiritual world of his created rational and moral creatures. Augustine offers a fascinating mental experiment. I emphasised in italics the most relevant sections.
"Let us take, then, the case of a wise man, such that his rational soul is already partaker of the unchangeable and eternal truth, so that he consults it about all his actions, nor does anything at all, which he does not by it know ought to be done, in order that by being subject to it and obeying it he may do rightly. Suppose now that this man, upon counsel with the highest reason of the divine righteousness, which he hears with the ear of his heart in secret, and by its bidding, should weary his body by toil in some office of mercy, and should contract an illness; and upon consulting the physicians, were to be told by one that the cause of the disease was overmuch dryness of the body, but by another that it was overmuch moisture; one of the two no doubt would allege the true cause and the other would err, but both would pronounce concerning proximate causes only, that is, corporeal ones. But if the cause of that dryness were to be inquired into, and found to be the self-imposed toil, then we should have come to a yet higher cause, which proceeds from the soul so as to affect the body which the soul governs. Yet neither would this be the first cause, for that doubtless was a higher cause still, and lay in the unchangeable wisdom itself, by serving which in love, and by obeying its ineffable commands, the soul of the wise man had undertaken that self-imposed toil; and so nothing else but the will of God would be found most truly to be the first cause of that illness. But suppose now in that office of pious toil this wise man had employed the help of others to co-operate in the good work, who did not serve God with the same will as himself, but either desired to attain the reward of their own carnal desires, or shunned merely carnal unpleasantnesses;—suppose, too, he had employed beasts of burden, if the completion of the work required such a provision, which beasts of burden would be certainly irrational animals, and would not therefore move their limbs under their burdens because they at all thought of that good work, but from the natural appetite of their own liking, and for the avoiding of annoyance—suppose, lastly, he had employed bodily things themselves that lack all sense, but were necessary for that work, as e.g. grain, and wine, and oils, clothes, or money, or a book, or anything of the kind—certainly, in all these bodily things thus employed in this work, whether animate or inanimate, whatever took place of movement, of wear and tear, of reparation, of destruction, of renewal or of change in one way or another, as places and times affected them; pray, could there be, I say, any other cause of all these visible and changeable facts, except the invisible and unchangeable will of God, using all these, both bad and irrational souls, and lastly bodies, whether such as were inspired and animated by those souls, or such as lacked all sense, by means of that upright soul as the seat of His wisdom, since primarily that good and holy soul itself employed them, which His wisdom had subjected to itself in a pious and religious obedience?" ~ On the Trinity, 3.3. Emphasis added.
Therefore, it is only with God that "fixedly abide the causes of all unstable things" because he is the only unchangeable cause of both changeable causes and their effects. Now if this is the case, it is not surprising that Augustine adds that "the power of the will of God reaches through the spiritual creature [angels] even to visible and sensible effects of the corporeal creature. For where does not the wisdom of the omnipotent God work that which He wills, which reaches from one end to another mightily, and sweetly does order all things?" (3.2.6). God's sovereign causative activity, therefore, includes all existence, both in its material and its spiritual form, both the physical and material realm and the spiritual and moral realm.
"The will of God, 'who makes His angels spirits, and His ministers a flaming fire' [Heb 1:7; Sal. 103:4], presiding among spirits which are joined in perfect peace and friendship, and combined in one will by a kind of spiritual fire of charity, as it were in an elevated and holy and secret seat, as in its own house and in its own temple, thence diffuses itself through all things by certain most perfectly ordered movements of the creature; first spiritual, then corporeal; and uses all according to the unchangeable pleasure of its own purpose, whether incorporeal things or things corporeal, whether rational or irrational spirits, whether good by His grace or evil through their own will. But as the more gross and inferior bodies are governed in due order by the more subtle and powerful ones, so all bodies are governed by the living spirit; and the living spirit devoid of reason, by the reasonable living spirit; and the reasonable living spirit that makes default and sins, by the living and reasonable spirit that is pious and just; and that by God Himself, and so the universal creature by its Creator, from whom and through whom and in whom it is also created and established. And so it comes to pass that the will of God is the first and the highest cause of all corporeal appearances and motions. For nothing is done visibly or sensibly, unless either by command or permission from the interior palace, invisible and intelligible, of the supreme Governor, according to the unspeakable justice of rewards and punishments, of favor and retribution, in that far-reaching and boundless commonwealth of the whole creature." ~ On the Trinity, 3.4.9.

"Of all things that are changeable the unchangeable roots remain with Thee" – Ontology of Creation.
According to Augustine, there are in God all the ideas, examples, patterns of every single created thing (how exactly that happens I will not discuss here; this touches the philosophical and theological issue of the relationship between God and the so-called abstract objects).  
"God supreme and true, with His Word and Holy Spirit (which three are one), one God omnipotent, creator and maker of every soul and of every body; by whose gift all are happy who are happy through verity and not through vanity; who made man a rational animal consisting of soul and body, who, when he sinned, neither permitted him to go unpunished, nor left him without mercy; who has given to the good and to the evil, being in common with stones, vegetable life in common with trees, sensuous life in common with brutes, intellectual life in common with angels alone; from whom is every mode, every species, every order; from whom are measure, number, weight; from whom is everything which has an existence in nature, of whatever kind it be, and of whatever value; from whom are the seeds of forms and the forms of seeds, and the motion of seeds and of forms; who gave also to flesh its origin, beauty, health, reproductive fecundity, disposition of members, and the salutary concord of its parts; who also to the irrational soul has given memory, sense, appetite, but to the rational soul, in addition to these, has given intelligence and will; who has not left, not to speak of heaven and earth, angels and men, but not even the entrails of the smallest and most contemptible animal, or the feather of a bird, or the little flower of a plant, or the leaf of a tree, without an harmony, and, as it were, a mutual peace among all its parts—that God can never be believed to have left the kingdoms of men, their dominations and servitudes, outside of the laws of His providence." ~ The City of God, 5.11. Emphasis added.
In Augustine's view, the presence in God of the ideal forms and reasons of all things has important ontological implications. Through the creative act, these eternal and ideal reasons manifest themselves in the created order through the so-called seminal reasons or principles. 
"We worship that God who has appointed to the natures created by Him both the beginnings and the end of their existing and moving; who holds, knows, and disposes the causes of things; who has created the virtue of seeds; who has given to what creatures He would a rational soul, which is called mind; who has bestowed the faculty and use of speech; who has imparted the gift of foretelling future things to whatever spirits it seemed to Him good; who also Himself predicts future things, through whom He pleases, and through whom He will, removes diseases who, when the human race is to be corrected and chastised by wars, regulates also the beginnings, progress, and ends of these wars who has created and governs the most vehement and most violent fire of this world, in due relation and proportion to the other elements of immense nature; who is the governor of all the waters; who has made the sun brightest of all material lights, and has given him suitable power and motion; who has not withdrawn, even from the inhabitants of the nether world, His dominion and power; who has appointed to mortal natures their suitable seed and nourishment, dry or liquid; who establishes and makes fruitful the earth; who bountifully bestows its fruits on animals and on men; who knows and ordains, not only principal causes, but also subsequent causes; who has determined for the moon her motion; who affords ways in heaven and on earth for passage from one place to another; who has granted also to human minds, which He has created, the knowledge of the various arts for the help of life and nature; who has appointed the union of male and female for the propagation of offspring; who has favored the societies of men with the gift of terrestrial fire for the simplest and most familiar purposes, to burn on the hearth and to give light." ~ The City of God, 7.30.
Augustine's belief according to which there are "some hidden seeds of all things that are born corporeally and visibly ... concealed in the corporeal elements of this world" (On the Trinity, 3.8.13) leads him to offer the description of "pregnant" creation which is both fascinating and philosophically relevant for the history of Christian thought.
"All these things in the way of original and beginning have already been created in a kind of texture of the elements, but they come forth when they get the opportunity. For as mothers are pregnant with young, so the world itself is pregnant with the causes of things that are born; which are not created in it, except from that highest essence, where nothing either springs up or dies, either begins to be or ceases. But the applying from without of adventitious causes, which, although they are not natural, yet are to be applied according to nature, in order that those things which are contained and hidden in the secret bosom of nature may break forth and be outwardly created in some way by the unfolding of the proper measures and numbers and weights which they have received in secret from Him who has ordered all things in measure and number and weight: this is not only in the power of bad angels, but also of bad men." ~ On the Trinity, 3.9.16.
As it is relatively well known, Augustine's metaphysics and ontology of creation have important epistemological implications.

"The eternal reasons of things which are temporal and irrational do live" – Epistemology.
God alone "is the creator who is the chief former of these things. Neither can any one be this, unless He with whom primarily rests the measure, number, and weight of all things existing; and He is God the one Creator, by whose unspeakable power it comes to pass" (On the Trinity3.9.18). The Augustinian principles mentioned so far are, unsurprisingly, also epistemological in character. According to Augustine, in God there are also the archetypal and perfect eternal reasons and truths that we, humans, use in order to perceive, interpret, know, jusge, and understand both the physical and the spiritual worlds. Regarding the former, Augustine says what follows. 
"Whence also, even in the case of the images of things corporeal which are drawn in through the bodily sense, and in some way infused into the memory, from which also those things which have not been seen are thought under a fancied image, whether otherwise than they really are, or even perchance as they are—even here too, we are proved either to accept or reject, within ourselves, by other rules which remain altogether unchangeable above our mind, when we approve or reject anything rightly. For both when I recall the walls of Carthage which I have seen, and imagine to myself the walls of Alexandria which I have not seen, and, in preferring this to that among forms which in both cases are imaginary, make that preference upon grounds of reason; the judgment of truth from above is still strong and clear, and rests firmly upon the utterly indestructible rules of its own right; and if it is covered as it were by cloudiness of corporeal images, yet is not wrapt up and confounded in them." ~ Augustine, On the Trinity, 9.6.10.
Without necessarily degrading sensorial knowledge, yet Augustine is clearly more interested in the intellectual knowledge of spiritual truths and principle.
"It makes a difference, whether, under that or in that darkness, I am shut off as it were from the clear heaven; or whether (as usually happens on lofty mountains), enjoying the free air between both, I at once look up above to the calmest light, and down below upon the densest clouds. For whence is the ardor of brotherly love kindled in me, when I hear that some man has borne bitter torments for the excellence and steadfastness of faith? And if that man is shown to me with the finger, I am eager to join myself to him, to become acquainted with him, to bind him to myself in friendship. And accordingly, if opportunity offers, I draw near, I address him, I converse with him, I express my goodwill towards him in what words I can, and wish that in him too in turn should be brought to pass and expressed goodwill towards me; and I endeavor after a spiritual embrace in the way of belief, since I cannot search out so quickly and discern altogether his innermost heart. I love therefore the faithful and courageous man with a pure and genuine love. But if he were to confess to me in the course of conversation, or were through unguardedness to show in any way, that either he believes something unseemly of God, and desires also something carnal in Him, and that he bore these torments on behalf of such an error, or from the desire of money for which he hoped, or from empty greediness of human praise: immediately it follows that the love with which I was borne towards him, displeased, and as it were repelled, and taken away from an unworthy man, remains in that form, after which, believing him such as I did, I had loved him; unless perhaps I have come to love him to this end, that he may become such, while I have found him not to be such in fact. And in that man, too, nothing is changed: although it can be changed, so that he may become that which I had believed him to be already. But in my mind there certainly is something changed, viz., the estimate I had formed of him, which was before of one sort, and now is of another: and the same love, at the bidding from above of unchangeable righteousness, is turned aside from the purpose of enjoying, to the purpose of taking counsel. But the form itself of unshaken and stable truth, wherein I should have enjoyed the fruition of the man, believing him to be good, and wherein likewise I take counsel that he may be good, sheds in an immoveable eternity the same light of incorruptible and most sound reason, both upon the sight of my mind, and upon that cloud of images, which I discern from above, when I think of the same man whom I had seen. Again, when I call back to my mind some arch, turned beautifully and symmetrically, which, let us say, I saw at Carthage; a certain reality that had been made known to the mind through the eyes, and transferred to the memory, causes the imaginary view. But I behold in my mind yet another thing, according to which that work of art pleases me; and whence also, if it displeased me, I should correct it. We judge therefore of those particular things according to that [form of eternal truth], and discern that form by the intuition of the rational mind. But those things themselves we either touch if present by the bodily sense, or if absent remember their images as fixed in our memory, or picture, in the way of likeness to them, such things as we ourselves also, if we wished and were able, would laboriously build up: figuring in the mind after one fashion the images of bodies, or seeing bodies through the body; but after another, grasping by simple intelligence what is above the eye of the mind, viz., the reasons and the unspeakably beautiful skill of such forms." ~ Augustine, On the Trinity, 9.6.11.
Augustine explains how, for instance, this happens in the context of the inner generation and consequent exercise of human verbal language. He offers a sort of phenomenology of the human word. 
"We behold, then, by the sight of the mind, in that eternal truth from which all things temporal are made, the form according to which we are, and according to which we do anything by true and right reason, either in ourselves, or in things corporeal; and we have the true knowledge of things, thence conceived, as it were as a word within us, and by speaking we beget it from within; nor by being born does it depart from us. And when we speak to others, we apply to the word, remaining within us, the ministry of the voice or of some bodily sign, that by some kind of sensible remembrance some similar thing may be wrought also in the mind of him that hears—similar, I say, to that which does not depart from the mind of him that speaks. We do nothing, therefore, through the members of the body in our words and actions, by which the behavior of men is either approved or blamed, which we do not anticipate by a word uttered within ourselves. For no one willingly does anything, which he has not first said in his heart." ~ Augustine, On the Trinity, 9.7.10.
Conclusion
As I mostly commented Augustine through his own words, my own comments were not particularly in-depth. Here I simply wanted to show one example of the very deep and numerous theological and philosophical references that are virtually everywhere in Augustine's Confessions. As the sentence by Augustine I have here discussed is (like countless other Augustinian passages,) pregnant with meaning, so, according to Augustine, creation is full of God's activity (in the way Augustine qualifies that).

©

Addendum (May 24, 2023): Dr. David Noe from Latin Per Diem has produced a very helpful video where he parses the passage from Augustine which I discussed here.